CAN CHILDREN DO PHILOSOPHY?
by Karin Murris
Abstract
Some philosophers claim that young children cannot
do philosophy. The aim of my paper is to examine some of those claims, and to
put forward arguments against them. Our beliefs that children cannot do
philosophy are based on philosophical assumptions about children, their
thinking, and about philosophy. Many of those assumptions remain unquestioned
by critics of Philosophy with Children. My conclusion is that the idea that
very young children can do philosophy has not only significant consequences for
how we should educate young children, but also for how adults should do
philosophy; and that further research is urgently needed.
Introduction
“Philosophy is often thought of as a body of
knowledge; but this idea makes little sense, because for virtually every
significant statement that one philosopher makes, it is possible to find
another who will disagree with it. It is better to consider philosophy as a
method of enquiring into very fundamental questions that do not yield to the
methods of science. In the Western tradition, since the time of Plato, this
method can be characterised by a form of relentless questioning, in which the
answer to one question only leads to a further question, and so on, and on and
on. Readers of Plato will know what I mean. And so will parents of small
children.”
Peter Singer
The debate as to
whether philosophy is suitable for children is an ancient one. Philosophers
since as long ago as Plato have had plenty to say on the subject – most of it
negative. The debate continues unabated, but is often complicated by the
confusion between ‘doing’ philosophy as a subject – i.e., studying the idea’s
of the world’s great thinkers since the Greeks – and ‘philosophising’, i.e.,
thinking about any question in a philosophical way. The debate is complicated
further by disagreement over what the term ‘philosophy’ actually means.
British
philosopher John Wilson, for example, has argued that the ‘Philosophy for
Children’ (P4C)1 movement suffers
from educational ideology. The ideology he refers to is the assumption that
philosophy is something like: a focus on questioning, enquiry, and being
critical (Wilson, 1992, p. 17). Wilson criticises the P4C movement for not
being entirely clear about what exactly is understood by philosophy. Similarly,
John White and Richard Kitchener object to the lack of “higher-order thinking”
when young children philosophise about concepts and principles.
Apples and pears
The way in which
critics of Philosophy with Children (PwC) often compare child philosophers with
adult philosophers is based on a category mistake. They are not comparing one
group of apples with another group of
apples, they are comparing apples
with pears. PwC proponent Gareth Matthews admits that children can be less
“disciplined” and less “rigorous” than some
adults, but he cautions comparing children with just any adult (Matthews, 1994, p. 17). After all, there is a great
variety among adults in the ability to be involved in rigorous and disciplined
philosophical enquiry. Young
children will discuss the kind of problems and raise the kind of questions
academic philosophers are puzzled about when
they have just started doing philosophy. For when comparing children’s
ability to do philosophy with that of adults it has to be clear whether we are
referring to:
·
trained and
qualified academic philosophers;
·
adult students in
philosophy (who have just started);
·
non-philosophically
trained adults.
The only fair
comparison is that between children and the second group of adults (students
who have just started); and even then we have to be cautious, because:
·
it is tempting to evaluate children’s thinking
through the language they use, and the younger the child, the more likely that
they cannot verbalise properly some of their thoughts;
·
it is possible that young children’s thinking
differs from that of adults. In evaluating their talk, adult researchers run
the risk of evaluating children’s thinking by comparing it with how adults
reason in order to make sense of their experiences. Children’s fantasy could be
a different – but not less rational – way of making meaning (see below).
Even if Richard
Kitchener were correct in his claim that young children cannot engage in
“higher‑order thinking” - he refers to “considerable evidence”, but fails to
explain what this evidence consists of (Kitchener, 1990, p. 422) - not many
non-philosophically trained adults are
capable of what Kitchener describes as “formal operational thinking”, that is,
the ability to not only hypothesise about contrary-to-fact situations, and to
draw logical conclusions, but to apply this knowledge to other, similar cases.
Neither are many non-philosophically trained adults capable of ‘post-formal
operational thinking’, that is, doing meta-ethics, meta-logic, etc. (Kitchener,
1990, p. 440). In contrast to non-philosophically trained children and adults, philosophically trained children do have the inclination to think
about their own thinking (e.g. in the meta-dialogues) in that they think and
talk about their ideas and relate them to what other children have said,
showing the structure of the dialogue as they speak (See e.g. McCall, 1990;
Murris, 1997).
The issue is
further complicated by the fact that even if it were true that young children
(who had just started doing philosophy) in comparison with adults (who had just
started doing philosophy) were less capable of doing philosophy, the conclusion
does not follow that children should not be taught philosophy. After all,
primary children do not ‘do’, for example, mathematics or history as capably as
professional mathematicians or historians. Does it, therefore, follow that,
either they do not do ‘real’ mathematics or ‘real’ history, or that they should
not do those subjects?
Philosopher Mary
Midgley in her response to journalist Jenny Turner’s rejection of philosophical
enquiry with children in The Guardian,
points out that:
“Of
course children’s arguments are not the same as the discussions of university
students. But then neither is a child’s eager participation when his or her
parents are mending the garage just like the work which that child may do later
as an engineering student. In both, what matters is to pick up the general
spirit of such activities, to start seeing them as interesting and possible.
And if one does not do this as a child, it is much harder to do it later.
Philosophy has never been a quarantined enclave for professionals, any more
than literature has, and it would die if it were to become so” (“Letters to the
Editor”, The Guardian, 18 June 1996, p. 14).
What is important
is that children can, and do, pick up “the general spirit of such activities”,
and, as such, are being taught a philosophical form of life. Or, as Clyde Evans
put it, the children are introduced to philosophical issues and philosophical
commitments – the sort of commitments to certain procedural principles that
make philosophical discourse possible. He mentions: impartiality, objectivity,
consistency, comprehensiveness, respect for other persons, searching for
defensible reasons, and consideration only of relevant criteria (Evans, 1978,
p. 162).
Abstract concepts
do not simply ‘develop’. In order to use concepts in a sophisticated manner,
thinking about them in a disciplined and systematic manner helps to ‘expand’
them. This is something non-philosophically and non-academically trained adults
find hard to do (something they share with non-philosophically trained
children). Training in philosophical enquiry, rather than age, seems the crucial factor here; and until children have done
philosophy throughout their nursery and primary education we should not
generalise about children’s abilities to do philosophy.
On the other
hand, it could be argued that philosophy is somehow an exceptional subject,
which renders it’s teaching to young children either inappropriate or
impossible. Unlike other subjects, it is thinking itself philosophers think
about. This, as I will argue below, actually works in favour of the argument
that young children can do philosophy.
Lack of meta-level reflection
Would it be
possible to invalidate the criticism that children cannot do philosophy, by
giving examples of children saying the same thing as a famous adult
philosopher, only formulated in a simpler vocabulary? This is a tactic often
used not only in PwC (Matthews, 1994, pp. 10, 11, 37; McCall, 1990), but also
justified by PwC proponents as the correct procedure. 2
This would be unlikely to convince
Kitchener, who argues that examples like these merely show that children are
capable of “single, one‑time performances” or “philosophical one‑liners”
(Kitchener, 1990, p. 426). I agree with his methodological objection that short
anecdotes, or philosophical “one-liners”, can be misleading. The danger of
using short anecdotes is that particular theories are easily projected into
children’s words; and the problem with “one-liners” is that, even if children express a philosophical
thought, only questioning will bring out to what extent they are capable of sustaining this philosophical way of
thinking. I disagree, however, with what would count as evidence for Kitchener.
What would convince Kitchener is if children “questioned on a one‑one basis
about their comments” could “elaborate upon their views, and rationally defend
them” (Kitchener, 1990, pp. 426, 427).
Kitchener misses
the collaborative dimension of groups of children thinking together like ‘one
big head’3,
building on each other’s ideas. The goal of philosophical enquiry with children
transcends the thinking of any one individual. The insights acquired could
never have been reached by the individuals alone. So, the question should
rather be, ‘Is a community of young children such that its members are capable
of critically questioning each other and defending their points of view over a
long period of time?’.
John White
specifies evidence as follows: children should be able to demonstrate, not only
that they can be logical, or that they can reason, but that they can take a “higher‑order stance to reasoning”
(White, 1992, p. 75). (The founder of the Philosophy for Children Movement,
Matthew Lipman reportedly claims that children start philosophising when they
ask the question ‘why?’; elsewhere Lipman claims that philosophy begins when
children start to question the meaning of words. 4)
Like White,
Kitchener is sceptical of the idea that young children can do ‘real’
philosophy. He claims that although children are capable of doing ‘concrete
philosophy’, they are not capable of
doing ‘abstract philosophy’ (Kitchener, 1990, pp. 427, 428). Matthews, Lipman,
Pritchard and others, show only that children are capable of concrete philosophising when giving
examples of children talking about: ‘death’, ‘dreaming’, ‘bravery’, ‘time‑travel’,
‘the material composition of cheese’, ‘the ship of Theseus’, and ‘sharing the
television set’. Kitchener claims that those philosophical dialogues are about
concrete examples, rather than general principles, and that children cannot
grasp the principle qua principle underlying
a concrete case, e.g., the ontological principle of, for example, what
constitutes identity over time in the case of the ship of Theseus.
Is it indeed true
to say that children cannot abstract from concrete examples to make more
general conclusions and apply those to other, similar, concrete cases, make
analogies, etc.?
The Ship of
Theseus is one of the subjects of a philosophical dialogue among children
facilitated and reported by Gareth Matthews (Matthews, 1984, pp. 37‑48). The
Ship of Theseus was an ancient ship of which all the boards had been replaced
one by one over a period of time, until all the boards were new. This raises
the philosophical problem whether this ship can still be called the same old
ship, and, if not, when and why did the old ship cease to exist.
Also, the problem of identity5 is
further complicated by the fact that the planks which have been taken out could
be used to construct a second identical ship (Curnow, 1995, pp. 25,26).
A child called
Donald6,
formulates the problem as follows: “Is the ship the old ship, or is the ship
just a model, a replica, a copy of the original ship?”. After a transcript of
the subsequent dialogue, Matthews comments on the ability of some of the
children in this classroom to distinguish between knowing whether it would be the old ship, from whether people
would recognise it as the old ship
(Matthews, 1984, pp. 41, 42). What Matthews shows is that at least some children can make this distinction.
But does Donald understand the ontological principle qua principle? Could he apply the principle of what constitutes
identity over time, not only to this particular case of the ship Theseus, but
also to other similar cases?
The dialogue that
follows shows that the children subsequently use analogies. They transfer the
problem to castles (how many bricks can we replace before it is not the same
castle any more) and cars (windows, wheels and doors can be replaced but unless
the engine stays the same it is not the same car any more). However, these are
concrete examples. Would children struggle more if they had to apply this
distinction to the more abstract problem of, for example, personal identity?
This issue could
be settled perhaps by empirical evidence of children doing exactly that.
Matthews reports elsewhere of children making the analogy between the gradual
replacements of planks with the gradual displacement of cells in their own
bodies (Matthews, 1994, p. 6). But this would not satisfy the critics. They
claim that children would have to show that they can think about the principle
itself, like Aristotle did, when he postulated his theory of substance (Kitchener, 1990, p. 427).
However, Matthews
does not seem too concerned to meet his critics’ demands. He settles for less,
and argues for a relative and not an absolute distinction between philosophy
for adults and philosophy for children (Matthews, 1978, p. 68). He refuses to
use adult philosophy as a criterion for judging the philosophical dimension of
children’s thinking. Children are natural
philosophers (Matthews, 1994, p. 6), not cultivated philosophers – the two can never be the same, he claims.
The ‘cultivated’
adult philosopher cultivates the innocence necessary for philosophising, and
can therefore better rationally defend views expressed, but the adult –
according to Matthews – has lost a child’s natural sense of wonder about the
meaning of concepts, which disappears when a person starts to take for granted
the difference between the literal and the figurative use of language
(Matthews, 1978, p. 72).7
Therefore, it
would be better to say that Matthews does not claim that children philosophers are like adult philosophers, nor does he
claim that they should be like adult
philosophers. He seems to claim the reverse – that adult philosophers would be
better philosophers if they had more of the natural innocence of a child
(Matthews, 1978, p. 72).
Matthews gives
way unnecessarily to his opponents. What is this ‘real’ philosophy adult philosophers
are supposed to be doing? – ‘real philosophy’ as being the examination of
principles underlying particular
cases. Such philosophical activities have been heavily criticised by, for
example, adult philosopher Ludwig Wittgenstein, as a typical way of
unnecessarily creating philosophical problems.
Wittgenstein says
that philosophical problems, metaphorically speaking, are like a disease. 8 They arise when philosophers are misled by
the superficial grammar of our language. In the case of the philosophical
problem of identity (as in the Ship of Theseus), when a police officer asks
you: “Please prove your identity” it is possible to be misled into thinking
that “identity” is the name of a thing –
emphasised by the fact that a usual response would be to prove our
identity by showing a thing –
passport, driving licence, etc. – in response to the demand. It is the language
learned from an early age that spreads this ‘disease’ – i.e., assuming a
name presupposes the existence of an
object (Curtis, 1985, pp. 10‑19; Clark, 1990, pp. 247‑265).
What is the cure
to this ‘disease’ of philosophical problem seeking? According to Wittgenstein,
it is the task of philosophers, not to solve,
but to dissolve philosophical
problems by looking at the everyday use of the concepts involved. He
writes:
“...The problems are solved, not by giving new
information, but by rearranging what we have always known. Philosophy is a
struggle against the bewitchment of our intellect by means of language”
(Wittgenstein, 1958, par 109). 9
That is, look how
words are actually used in everyday language. It is our misunderstanding of how
everyday language actually functions that has created philosophical problems.
If we apply this to the example described above, then – following Wittgenstein
– we could say that the attempt to find an ontological principle to explain
identity over time, in order to postulate philosophical notions such as
“essence”, “substance”, etc., are a blind alley. Philosophers should not ask
themselves “What is identity?”, but instead concentrate on how words such as
“identity” are actually used in everyday circumstances. An enquiry about the
meaning of concepts embedded in their lifeworlds is exactly what young children
do when engaged in philosophical enquiries.
It is when
concepts are taken out of the context of everyday life in which they are used,
that philosophical problems are created. One such problem is to look at a
principle qua principle. Some adult
philosophers argue that this should be transmittable to child philosophers if
they are to do ‘real’ philosophy. Wittgenstein argues – and I agree with him –
that this ‘disease’ should be ‘cured’ in adult philosophers. Making it a
criterion with which to judge children’s philosophy is insufficient without
offering further arguments.
What is peculiar about children?
What is so
peculiar about children that we are
prompted to ask the question as to whether they can do philosophy in the first
place? Neo-Aristotelian assumptions often underlie criticisms of PwC. The generally accepted belief is that we are a ‘tabula rasa’ when born (or conceived?);
and that all our knowledge comes from experience, and doing philosophy requires
knowledge upon which to reflect. Therefore, the older we are, the more is
‘written’ on our ‘slate’, and therefore the more knowledge we have acquired.
Children have insufficient experience (i.e. knowledge) and as a result are not
capable of doing philosophy, the argument goes (e.g. Flay, 1978). For example,
Anthony O’Hear claims that children under the age of twenty do not know what
love is. Children should not be allowed to challenge moral or epistemological authority,
since children have neither knowledge, nor experience.10 Even
accepting that children have less experience (is it possible to quantify
experience?), it does not follow that they do not have sufficient experience to reflect, or that philosophical reflection will not help them
make their experiences more meaningful to them.
Neo-Aristotelian
beliefs do not blend well with Neo-Socratic or Kantian inspired pedagogies.
Socrates’ aim (according to Plato) was not to teach anything new, but to assist
people in giving birth to their knowledge, i.e., to help them remember what they already knew (before
chained in their present body). According to Kant we have a priori knowledge (e.g., causality, time, space, justice, freedom)
that make experience possible - experience
is a necessary, but not sufficient condition for knowledge. It may be the case
that not all conceptual knowledge is acquired
through learning a language and growing up (through experience).
I detect similar
Neo-Aristotelian assumptions in John White’s criticism - he claims that the
acquisition of knowledge of concepts takes place empirically. He argues for a difference between the kinds of
questions children ask and the kinds of questions adults ask. Children ask
questions in order to find out how to use concepts. Adult philosophers, on the
other hand, already knowing how to use the concepts “...are interested in
mapping it from a higher‑order perspective” (White, 1992, p. 75). In his paper The Roots of Philosophy, White rightly
points out that a question is not, in and by itself, philosophical. It is the context that makes a question
philosophical, in the sense that the context would determine if a question
“calls into doubt a very ordinary notion” (White, 1992, p. 74).
White also points
out that the intention of the
questioner is very important in determining whether a question is
philosophical. It is for this reason that he believes that, because children’s
intentions differ from those of adults, children are not philosophers. He
writes:
“Children want to know how to use the
concept; philosophers, who have no trouble using it, are interested in mapping
it from a higher‑order perspective, and usually in the pursuit of larger
theoretical enquiries. Needless to say, too, philosophers are only interested
in those concepts which present philosophical problems, whereas the point just
made about children can apply to their acquisition of all kinds of concepts – of cats, rivers, computers” (White, 1992,
pp. 75, 76).
Children are not
philosophising, but “simply on the way to acquiring the concept” (White, 1992,
p. 76). Is it true to say that children merely want “to know how to use the
concept”, and that adults “have no trouble using it”? Also, is an enquiry about
“cats, rivers, computers” always non-philosophical?
Teachers who do
philosophy with young children accept that ‘being reasonable’ is not a sufficient condition for calling an
enquiry a philosophical enquiry. It
is not just the fact that someone is reasoning, but also what s/he is reasoning
about that is a criterion for
distinguishing philosophical talk from ordinary talk.
This is
acknowledged, for example, by Ann Margaret Sharp and Laurance Splitter who
insist that an enquiry should focus on the analysis and formation of concepts of a certain kind. They are
problematic, but significant, abstract concepts. These are the sorts of
concepts we use to think and communicate with, and we also use them as a basis
for our actions. We use them in everyday life. They are central and common. All
of us use those concepts to make sense of the world we live in, or, put
differently, to structure reality with (Splitter & Sharp, 1995).
Philosophical
thinking is complex thinking (Lipman,
1991; Cam, 1995). It is, because “[p]hilosophical concepts distinguish
themselves from those of everyday life by their generality, by their abstract
character, but especially by their complexity: most philosophical concepts are
not simple class concepts which can be dealt with by prototype learning” (Leeuw
& Mostert, 1987, p. 94). For example, we do not learn the concept ‘person’
by simply pointing at various concrete individuals. It does not tell us anything
about what it is that makes us different from our goldfish. However, for young
and old alike, it is not only very difficult to answer questions such as “What
is a ‘person’?”, or “What do I mean by ‘time’?”, but also crucial to making
sense of our experiences, ourselves and the world we live in.
The class of
concepts enquired into by children, however, is larger than that of traditional
philosophy. The reason is that children themselves generate the concepts and
the questions they find important. It does not follow, however, that such
enquiries cannot be philosophical. A great deal depends upon the teacher’s
skills in facilitating the thinking of the children, and in helping them to
build on each other’s ideas, while at the same time ‘probing’ for the philosophical.
I have witnessed an enquiry starting off with the statement “Cows can’t fly”,
which quickly turned into an enquiry about the moral implications of calling a
group of molecules ‘beef’ rather than ‘cow’.11 Similarly, starting off with the concept ‘computer’
and asking the question ‘Do computers think?’ can easily lead into
philosophical discussions with young and old - both knowing how to use the concept, i.e., referring to a
particular physical object. Of course, there are times when children ask questions
and enquire into concepts, because they do not know how to use a particular
concept, but this is not always the case. Even when we know how to use a
concept, philosophical puzzlement remains - especially when we have just been
initiated into a particular language and culture. This could be young children’s philosophical advantage (see
below).
What is involved
in understanding or knowing concepts is in itself an intriguing philosophical
topic. Kieran Egan argues that very young children already use abstract
concepts (without being to define them), and that they do this through fantasy
(Egan, 1988, p. 26). The concepts involved in making sense of stories with such
characters as smurfs, talking teddy bears, giants and monsters, are, for
example, ‘good and bad’, ‘big and little’, ‘fear and security’, ‘nature and
culture’. Egan maintains that pre-literate children’s thinking is different
from that of older children or adults. He calls it ‘mythical thinking’: a kind
of thinking with “its own complex logic and...this logic is not an opposite to
rational thought” (Egan, 1988, p. 39), but a foundation for rational thinking. It involves techniques of
thinking that rely on resources available in oral cultures (Egan, 1988, pp. 42,
43) – the kind of thinking prior to the internalisation of literacy. As a
result of literacy – the technology of writing – thought is restructured to
focus more on knowledge content or psychological development, and makes it
easier to reflect upon the meaning of what has to be memorised (Egan, 1988, pp.
51‑53, 59). Egan argues that this kind of thinking is certainly not
‘primitive’, and only less ‘abstract’ when we mean by abstraction the kind that
depends heavily on writing. The written word is much less charged than the
spoken word “...with the direct energy of the speaker’s body, and so the
speaker’s hopes, fears, wants, needs, intentions, and so on” (Egan, 1988, p.
70). It is the written word (internalised literacy) that makes our rationality
‘disembedded’ – i.e., not embedded in one’s lifeworld (Egan, 1988, p. 65).
Since the Enlightenment, the notion of ‘disembedded rationality’ has become
prevalent in Western culture in order to keep separate what one is thinking
about (objective knowledge content) and the subject who is doing the thinking
with all her feelings, hopes, and fears.
The ideal of
‘disembedded rationality’ makes it possible to discuss the meaning of a word‑as‑such,
outside the particular context in which the word is used. In this light, the
work of many philosophers can be seen as a search for the absolute, universal
meaning of a particular concept independent of its use in particular
circumstances (e.g., the Platonic Forms). This is still an ideal for many
philosophers, and is used as an argument against the idea that children can do
philosophy – e.g., Richard Kitchener’s claim that children can do only
‘concrete philosophy’ and not ‘abstract philosophy’; or, John White when he
argues that ‘real’ philosophers are interested only in those concepts which
present philosophical problems, not concepts such as ‘cats’, ‘rivers’, or,
‘computers’.
As pointed out
before, Wittgenstein warns us against catching this ‘disease’ suffered by many
philosophers – the unhealthy activity of philosophical problem-seeking by
taking concepts out of the context of everyday meaning. It does not make sense
to establish the meaning of words outside the contexts in which they are being
used (‘embodied’) in everyday life. With the philosophical critique of the
Western notion of ‘disembodied rationality’, awareness is growing that
children’s thinking is not inferior to that of adults, and that children
deserve to be listened to.
Egan argues that
children do think abstractly in the
sense that they use abstract concepts, such as ‘brave’, ‘fair’, ‘good’,
‘friend’, but not dissociated from their lifeworld as literacy enables and
encourages them to do (Egan, 1988, pp. 75, 90, 91). This would have
consequences for what adults understand the discipline of philosophy to be.
Mythical thinking is excluded from philosophical thinking only when we adopt a
narrow meaning of rationality.
What have adult philosophers lost?
Much of our
current educational thinking has been influenced by Swiss psychologist Jean
Piaget. An underlying philosophical assumption of Piagetian theory is that
children’s reasoning will develop automatically as children get older.
Moreover, an attempt to hasten this process will be a waste of time – perhaps
even regarded as educational malpractice (Gazzard, 1985, p. 11). In this view,
it is assumed that children’s development goes through irreversible, necessary
age‑related stages. This stage‑theory of cognitive development is reflected in
how educational curricula for primary education have been designed. The sort of
educational material taught, and how it is being taught, has to conform to the
particular intellectual capacities characteristic of the child’s age. Thus, the
educator focuses on the child’s age,
and not the child itself, running the risk that too much importance is given to
what children have in common (their age) instead of what makes them different
from one another (different abilities). Secondly, at most, the different stages
describe what children of a
particular age group are intellectually capable of, but, as Ann Gazzard points
out: “...now [stage theory of cognitive development] serves to define the range
of thought children are capable of” (Gazzard, 1985, p. 11). We do not know yet
the effect on the intellectual development of the young child, of long‑term
exposure to proper philosophy‑tuition.
In the last two
decades, much effort has been put into reinterpreting Piaget’s conclusions
drawn from psychological experiments. Margaret Donaldson argues that, not his findings as such are suspect, but that
the conclusions drawn from those findings are wrong (Donaldson, 1978, p. 23).
Empirical evidence for this conclusion is given by constructing similar
experiments, but in situations that make
sense to the child (Donaldson, 1978, p. 23; Sutherland, 1992, p. 15). For
example, in an attempt to demonstrate how ego‑centric children are, Piaget
conducted an experiment to show that children under the age of eight do not
have the ability to take account of someone else’s point of view – literally.
In his experiment, a child sits at a table with three different mountains on
it. A doll is placed somewhere else round the table. Most children cannot show
or describe what the doll sees. Donaldson contests Piaget’s conclusion that
children are “unable to ‘decentre’ in imagination” (Donaldson, 1978, p. 20),
which is a crucial requirement for thinking and reasoning well – because if a
child cannot shift between different points of view, she cannot make valid
inferences (Donaldson, 1978, p. 41). I have plenty of anecdotal evidence from
my own children that they can
decentre in imagination. For example, my youngest son, when he was 18 months,
expressed sympathy for his favourite Teletubbies doll (called ‘Lala’) lying on
the radiator. Walking towards the radiator, he said: “Lala hot”, picked her up
and cuddled her.
The unquestioned
assumption in developmental theories is that the goal of the process is
maturity – each stage is followed by one that is ‘better’, more mature. This is
what Matthews calls “evolutionary bias” (Matthews, 1994, p. 17). The point he
makes is that this kind of bias might not be appropriate for philosophy, the
reasons being that the better handling of philosophical questions is not
guaranteed by just growing up. Secondly, maturity often brings “staleness” and
“uninventiveness” (Matthews, 1994, p. 18) to the exploration of philosophical
ideas, while children are often “fresh and inventive thinkers”. It opens up the
possibility that philosophy as a discipline could learn something from children
engaged in philosophical enquiry. After all, each generation has to find its
own answers to philosophical questions (Leeuw, 1991, p. 13; Lipman & Sharp,
1978, pp. IX & X). There is a danger in philosophy that too many
conventions remain unquestioned. Therefore, rather than an asset, Van der Leeuw
argues that it could be a disadvantage for adults to be acquainted with the
philosophical tradition. Children’s lack
of knowledge of many of culture’s conventions might put them in an advantageous
position (Leeuw, 1991, p. 13). Matthews claims that good teachers of philosophy
remember the questions they had when they were a child. Otherwise philosophy
loses its urgency and much of its point (Matthews, 1994, p. 14). Robert
Mulvaney stipulates that philosophy with children may help “to preserve the
child in the philosopher”. He argues that:
“One of the tragedies of the grownup is his
loss of a sense of wonder, curiosity and playfulness, in short, of childhood.
But these emotions are central to philosophical enquiry. Perhaps by starting
philosophy earlier and seeing to it that it continues throughout school,
grownups will rediscover suppressed reservoirs of playfulness and leisure”
(Mulvaney, 1993, p. 400).
Thirdly,
following Plato and Descartes, philosophy is the epistemological pursuit of
‘starting all over again’, i.e., finding out for ourselves “...that I really do
know whatever it is I claim to know” (Matthews, 1994, p. 18). One necessary
condition for this philosophical exercise is the abandonment of cherished
beliefs and assumptions – something that is much harder for adults, whose
beliefs often have become firmly ‘rooted’ habits of thought. After
all, it was American philosopher, William James, who said: “A great many people
think they are thinking when they are merely rearranging their prejudices”. 12
Children’s lack
of knowledge about culture’s conventions forces them to take a ‘Cartesian
stance’, and to start from scratch when thinking about philosophical questions.
As a result, their answers to philosophical questions are bound to be more
original than those of adults (Leeuw & Mostert, 1987). Van der Leeuw claims
that it is for this reason that “[c]hildren’s thinking shows us another side of
the world, that is how the world could have been” (Leeuw, 1991, p. 13). The
world as‑it‑is, is too often taken for granted by adults – including adult
philosophers. So children’s lack of experience could be an advantage rather
than a disadvantage when they do philosophy (Leeuw, 1991, p. 14).
Throughout Gareth
Matthews’ works we find the idea that children are the ‘natural’ philosophers,
in contrast to adult philosophers who cultivate young children’s sense of
wonder. This is clear, for example, when he claims that philosophising adults
“...try to be little children again – even if only temporarily” (Matthews, 1994,
p. 18). Philosophy is not ‘immature’. Philosophy is naive perhaps, but it is a
“profound naiveté” (Matthews, 1994, p. 34).
To summarise,
what we mean by ‘being a child’ or ‘childhood’ is crucial to answering the
question of whether children can do philosophy. Merely assuming that childhood
is connected to a particular biological, psychological or social age is
unsatisfactory. It also limits cognitive development to include merely logico‑mathematical
thinking, and ignores imaginative development.
This bias has its
philosophical roots in Plato’s philosophy, in particular the Simile of the Cave (Murris, 1997, pp
63-65). Plato associates episteme (knowledge)
with adulthood, and doxa (belief)
with childhood (Egan, 1988, p. 47). Both Plato and Aristotle believe that
rational theoretical understanding gives superior knowledge of reality (Egan,
1988, p. 47). For Plato, only educated adults can acquire knowledge of the
unchanging reality (the Platonic Forms, such as Goodness, Beauty, etc.) through
rational enquiry. Less rational beings – including children – have access only
to the world of appearances, i.e., of the world as it is perceived through our
senses. We perceive this or that beautiful object, we judge this or that action
to be a good one, but Beauty or Goodness‑as‑such (the Platonic Forms) cannot be
perceived through the senses.
Children cannot
get out of the cave – this world of appearances, which is the object of opinion
(doxa). According to Plato, it is the
(adult) philosopher who is in love with the truth, i.e., wants to know how the
world is, rather than how it appears to be, and because episteme is reserved for adults only,
children cannot ‘love the truth’, i.e., be a philosopher. Children can only
have ‘mere beliefs’ about the world.
An important
criticism of Piagetian frameworks is the one‑sided emphasis on the logical
aspects of children’s thinking – using mathematical thinking as its paradigm.
Canadian educationalist, Kieran Egan, argues that the “other half” of the child
as learner – the imaginative side –
has been neglected by many educational researchers (Egan, 1988, 1992, 1993).
Education is about not only what we gain, but also about minimising losses; and
what has been lost is “the ability to see that world as the child sees it,
transfigured by fantasy” (Egan, 1988, p. 20). This is an area of thinking which
is neglected in Piaget’s writing with his emphasis on logical‑mathematical
thinking.
Piaget called
children’s imaginative responses “mere romancing” (Matthews, 1980, p. 39‑41).
It ignores what is perhaps special about
childhood. Is it indeed true to say that childhood is something we leave
behind, and replace by the same, albeit
more mature? Or, can we make a claim for the uniqueness of childhood? What
exactly falls under the concept ‘child’ or ‘childhood’? Apart from culturally
and historically problematic, the concept ‘childhood’ is also philosophically problematic, because it
is philosophically very difficult to say exactly what the difference is between
children and adults (Matthews, 1994, p. 8; Bottery, 1990, p. 237). 13
What is philosophy?
Most philosophers
have struggled, but failed, to give a definition of ‘philosophy’ everyone
agrees with. It seems that there are no necessary and sufficient conditions
which can be formulated for calling something ‘philosophy’. Instead, Richard
Kitchener refers to philosophy as a ‘form of life’. What would such a
philosophical way of doing things look like? How can you recognise a particular
way of doing things as ‘philosophy’? Richard Kitchener suggests the following
characteristics:
·
thinking about a
philosophical issue (e.g., determinism versus free will);
·
raising
philosophical questions and being puzzled by things ordinarily taken for granted;
·
reading the great
philosophers;
·
constructing
arguments in support of certain kinds of conclusions;
·
engaging in
various kinds of conversations about philosophy;
·
not being able to
stop philosophising
(Kitchener, 1990, p. 425).
Kitchener describes what professional academic
philosophers do. However, it would be a naturalistic
fallacy to assume that therefore this is what philosophers ought to do. And this is precisely
Kitchener’s mistake. He claims that, independent of how old they are,
philosophers’ way of life ought to approximate the above list. He derives
‘ought’ from ‘is’; or, formulated differently, a prescriptive statement from a descriptive
statement, without, as David Hume pointed out, providing further
explanation or reasons (quoted in Williams, 1985, pp. 122, 123). Kitchener uses
the above criteria of a philosophical form of life to argue against the
possibility of children doing
philosophy. In doing so, he jumps from ‘is’ to ‘ought’ without further
justification. He argues fallaciously that because many academic philosophers
do philosophy in a particular way, children ought to do it in the same way.
Also, there is
not one (ideal) form of life. Forms
of life differ, depending on factors such as language, ways of doing things,
ways of thinking, place, and time. A 20th century philosophical form of life is
very different from that of, for example, Ancient Greece over 2,000 years ago
with its oral dimension and
practical orientation - philosophy as the art of living in preparation
for death (Hadot, 1995; Nussbaum,
1994).
Academic philosophy versus philosophy with children
Academic
philosophy is not PwC’s paradigm. On the contrary, it is partly a criticism of
it. The founder of the P4C movement, Matthew Lipman, compares academic
philosophy to memorising the inscriptions in a graveyard; the memorising of a
collection of names and dates.
Lipman writes:
“...when I advocated philosophy in the
schools, I was not talking about the traditional academic philosophy taught in
the graduate schools of the university. What I was talking about was a
philosophy redesigned and reconstructed so as to make it available and
acceptable and enticing to children. Moreover, the pedagogy by which the
subject was to be presented would have to be just as drastically redesigned as
the subject itself” (Lipman, 1991, p. 262).
Lipman uses the
notion of a ‘form of life’ to highlight the oft‑made distinction between
philosophy as a ‘body of knowledge’ and philosophising as the activity of doing philosophy. He writes:
“The paradigm of doing philosophy is the
towering, solitary figure of Socrates, for whom philosophy was neither an
acquisition or a profession but a way of life. What Socrates models for us is
not philosophy known or philosophy applied but philosophy practised. He challenges us to acknowledge that philosophy as deed,
as form of life, is something that any of us can emulate” (Lipman, 1988, p.
12).
A similar view is
expressed by Dutch philosopher and PwC proponent, Karel van der Leeuw, who
claims that many philosophy students learn a great deal of philosophy, but that
they barely learn to think. Rather than using academic philosophy as a
paradigm, he urges that “Philosophical thinking has to start with our
experience and has, in the end, to return to it” (Van der Leeuw, 1993, p. 36).
According to Van der Leeuw, the reason for this is that philosophical concepts
– in contrast to other abstract and general concepts, such as, mathematical
concepts – cannot be clarified and developed by definition alone, or without
referring to concrete experiences. Therefore, philosophy cannot consist merely
of learning the history of philosophical ideas. Each person has to connect
abstract philosophical concepts to concrete experiences. Philosophical enquiry
is an activity generated out of pure necessity, because all of us already give
answers to philosophical questions, either explicitly, or implicitly through
our actions (Leeuw, 1993, pp. 9, 36); and it makes a difference whether we do
it well or badly (Emmet, 1991, p. 18). Philosophy can be a suitable subject for
children if “...reconstructed in ways that suit their talents and their
interests” (Cam, 1995, p. 13). This reconstruction should be such that children
do not learn about philosophy, but do philosophy.
It would be wrong
to say that the distinction between practical philosophy, or philosophising, on
the one hand, and academic philosophy, or the study of a body of knowledge on
the other, is that clear-cut. Doing an academic degree in philosophy involves
studying the ‘great philosophers’. This means (ideally) entering into a
dialogue with those philosophers – all the time asking oneself (and the
philosopher) questions and looking for possible answers to those questions.
There is also continuous dialogue with fellow students and tutors, and the
written dialogue in essay and paper form. Preparing for dissertations or papers
will, for example, involve reading articles in philosophy journals. Despite its
sterility, this is still entering an ongoing dialogue. One hopes that people
start the study of philosophy because they feel that certain questions deserve
pondering and desperately need answering. The dialogue with others – including
famous, albeit mainly deceased, philosophers – should inspire many new
questions.
However, the way
philosophy is taught at universities, or at A-level, often
does not reflect this internal dialogue with other philosophers, and these
external dialogues in written form. The structure of many lectures and
workshops at philosophy departments worldwide does not have the form of a genuine
enquiry where real philosophising is taking place. This does not do justice to
the very heart of the philosophical enterprise
the activity of philosophical questioning and concept‑analyses with an
attitude of open-mindedness. Without such an attitude there would never have
been philosophy (however defined) in the first place.
Philosophical
questioning, concept-analysis and an open-minded attitude are necessary conditions for being a
philosopher, and an awareness seems to be growing among teachers of philosophy
that, in order for students to acquire the necessary skills and attitudes, the
way the subject is taught needs to be changed. A method needs to be used that
reflects the dialogical character of philosophical thinking. The ‘community of
philosophical enquiry’ methodology does justice to the very heart of the
philosophical enterprise in most respects, and therefore ought to be the philosophical form of life. It is what McCall calls
an “authentic” environment for reasoning to develop, because:
“...the children are inquiring into issues
about which there are no definitive answers, and so the procedure of inquiry,
in contrast say to asking the teacher or consulting an encyclopaedia, is a
generation procedure” (McCall, 1990, p. 41).
In other words,
there is a homogeneity between form (how we teach) and content (what we teach).
The community of enquiry pedagogy could also change traditional academic
philosophy to be more relevant, accessible to all, and non-elitist. PwC could
also change the traditional philosophical ideal of the passive, solitary,
rational thinker, to include dialogue, embodiment and the imagination. Slade
acknowledges the necessity of a reflective enquiry about the principles of
reason itself, and points at the moral duty to make that reflection available
to all students (Slade, 1994, p. 31).
I conclude that
answering the question ‘Can children do philosophy’ is much more
philosophically problematic than the critics of PwC make it out to be.
Reasoning defensively from an established academic position does not suffice -
further research is urgently needed into, for example, the thinking peculiar to
very young children, what concepts they are capable of reflecting upon, and how philosophy is taught
most effectively. An extensive and long
term research project following children’s philosophical progress from the age
of three into adulthood would be a good
step forward.
Until we have the
benefits of further research, my
temporary answer to the question ‘Can
children do philosophy?’ is poignantly formulated by Ann Sharp and Laurance
Splitter. They write:
“...there is some truth in the Piagetian
tradition which it would be perilous to ignore. Children do not benefit from
being bombarded with ‘adult’ words and theories which mean little to them, and
they (pretty much like the rest of us) are unlikely to grasp concepts which
cannot be instantiated or illustrated within the realms of their own
experience. On the other hand, abstract concepts to do with conservation,
causality, the mind, reality, personhood and truth may be within the grasp of
young children provided that they can find pathways to and from their own more
concrete experiences” (Splitter & Sharp, 1995, p 22).
It is up to us
adults to lay the “groundwork for the construction of these pathways” (Splitter
& Sharp, 1995, p 22). To do or not to do, is a choice we make. It is a
choice we adults are morally responsible for.
FOOTNOTES
1 The abbreviation ‘PwC’ is
used throughout this paper to refer to the practitioners of philosophy with
children. The term ‘P4C’ is used as an abbreviation for the proponents of the
‘Philosophy for Children’ programme developed by Matthew Lipman and colleagues
from the Institute for the Advancement of Philosophy for Children (IAPC) in the
USA. ‘PwC’ stands for a larger group of people than ‘P4C’ because not all
children’s philosophy teachers believe the IAPC material is the best
educational material with which to introduce young children to philosophy.
2 For example, Matthews
explains what the philosopher can do for the non‑philosophical parent or
teacher. The philosopher can “...collect examples of philosophical thinking in
young children and then, by linking those childish thoughts to our
philosophical tradition, help parents and teachers to recognise philosophy in
their children, respect it when it appears, and even participate in it and
encourage it on occasion.” From: Gareth Matthews. The Philosophy of Childhood. Cambridge (Mass), Harvard Univ. Press,
1994, p. 37.
3 I have taken the idea of
‘thinking with one big head’ from Jos
Kessels. Socrates op de Markt.
Amsterdam, Boom, p 218.
4 In an interview with Matthew
Lipman for the BBC documentary series about educational pioneers called The Transformers. The documentary about
philosophy for children, called Socrates
with six olds, was broadcast in
Autumn 1990.
5 For example,
adult philosopher Trevor Curnow understands this so‑called philosophical
problem of the Ship of Theseus to be both impossible and simple at the same
time. It is impossible for the logic of either/or, the logic of being, to
provide an answer to a problem about becoming, he says. I quote: “We cannot
transpose a logic from one world to another and expect it to work
automatically. The logic of either/or is derived from a world of fixed
identities. It is scarcely surprising if it begins to struggle when it is
applied to a world where change is a constant fact of life. The world of
becoming needs a logic of becoming”. From: Trevor Curnow. “Transcendence,
Logic, and Identity”, In: Philosophy Now,
No. 12, 1995, pp. 24‑26.
6 It is not entirely clear how
old Donald is, but somewhere between eight and eleven.
7 For example, Matthews
writes: “When a child assimilates from our culture the desensitizing thesis
that many uses of words are merely figurative or metaphorical, she or he loses
the fascination with the weft of words that inspires poetry and animates
philosophy.” From: “The Child as Natural Philosopher”, in M. Lipman and A. M.
Sharp (eds.). Growing up with Philosophy.
Temple Univ. Press, Philadelphia, 1978, p. 72.
8 From: Ludwig Wittgenstein. Philosophische Untersuchungen. Frankfurt
am Main, Suhrkamp, 1971, p. 255.
9 My translation. Literal
quote: “Alle Erklarung muss fort, und nur
beschreibung an ihre Stelle treten. Und diese Beschreibung empfängt ihr Licht,
d.i. ihren Zweck, von den philosophischen Problemen. Diese sind freilich keine
empirischen, sondern sie werden durch eine Einsicht in das Arbeiten unserer
Sprache gelöst, und zwar so, dass dieses erkannt wird; entgegen einem Trieb, es
misszuverstehen. Diese Probleme werden gelöst, nicht durch Beibringen neuer
Erfahrung, sondern durch Zusamenstellung des längst Bekannten. Die Philosophie
ist ein Kampf gegen die Verhexung unsres Verstandes durch die Mittel unserer
Sprache.” From: Ludwig Wittgenstein. Philosophische
Untersuchungen. Frankfurt am Main, Suhrkamp, 1971, par 109.
10 According
Anthony O’Hear when presenting his paper Philosophy and Knowledge on 15 April 1997 at an International
Philosophy for Children Conference at King’s College, London.
11 This was a philosophical
enquiry skillfully facilitated by Roger Sutcliffe at the American Community
School, London, December 1997.
12 I found this quote in a
leaflet announcing courses in philosophical enquiry, organised and written by
British philosopher Barbara Rae, and brought to my attention by Myrna Shoa.
13 The concept of childhood is
historically problematic, because childhood is in a sense a modern (adult)
invention, and also oppressive, according to John Holt. See: Judith Hughes.
“The Philosopher’s Child; In: Thinking,
Vol. 10, No. 1, p. 40. Children used to be regarded as “little people” no substantial differences were assumed
between the ways grown‑ups think and
children. However, their status and role in family and society has dramatically
changed since industrialisation. Children’s ‘experts’, ‘authorities’ on
childhood have since “construed them as creatures apart from their parents...”
From: David Kennedy. “Why Philosophy for Children Now”; Thinking, Vol. 10, no 3, pp. 2‑6. See also: Gareth Matthews. The Philosophy of Childhood. Cambridge
(Mass), Harvard Univ. Press, 1994, p. 8. It for this reason, for example, that
there never used to be separate children’s literature, and infants were
artistically represented as ‘miniature grown‑ups’ – with their heads drawn one‑eighth
of the body, rather than the one‑fourth which it is in reality. The concept of
childhood is also culturally problematic:
children are seen to be substantially different in various cultures. See, for
example: Sheila Kitzinger and Celia Kitzinger. “Obedience and Autonomy”,
Chapter Four in: Talking with Children;
About Things That Matter. London, Pandora, 1989, pp. 48‑74.
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Aristotle.
“Nicomachean Ethics”; In: McKeon, Richard (ed.). (1973), Introduction to Aristotle; 2nd ed. Chicago, Univ. of Chicago Press,
pp. 338-584..
Cam, Philip.
(1995), Thinking Together; Philosophical
Inquiry for the Classroom. Australian English Teaching Association &
Hale and Iremonger.
Clark, Stephen.
(1990), “On wishing there were unicorns”. Proceedings of the Aristotelian
Society, 1990, pp. 247-265.
Curnow, Trevor.
(1995), “Transcendence, Logic, and Identity”; In: Philosophy Now, No. 12, pp. 24-26.
Curtis, Barry.
(1985), “Wittgenstein and Philosophy for Children”. Thinking, Vol. 5, No. 4, pp. 10-19.
Donaldson,
Margaret. (1978), Children’s Minds.
London, Fontana.
Egan, Kieran.
(1988), Primary Understanding; Education
in Early Childhood. London, Routledge.
Egan, Kieran.
(1992), Imagination in Teaching and
Learning; ages 8-15. London, Routledge.
Egan, Kieran.
(1993), “The Other Half of the Child”; In: Lipman, Matthew (ed.). Thinking, Children and Education.
Montclair, Kendall/Hunt, pp. 301-306.
Emmet, E R.
(1991), “Learning to Philosophize”. Penguin Books, 1991.
Evans, Clyde.
(1978), “The Feasibility of Moral Education”; In: M. Lipman and A. M. Sharp
(eds.). Growing up with Philosophy.
Philadelphia, Temple Univ. Press, 1978, pp. 157-174.
Flay, Joseph.
(1978), “Is Ethics for Children Moral?”; In: M. Lipman and A. M. Sharp (eds.). Growing up with Philosophy.
Philadelphia, Temple Univ. Press, 1978, pp. 145-157.
Gazzard, Ann.
(1985), “Philosophy for Children and the Piagetian Framework”; In: Thinking, Vol. 5, No. 1.
Hadot, Pierre.
(1995), “Philoosphy as a Way of Life; Spiritual Exercises from Socrates to
Foucault”. Oxford, Blackwell.
Kessels, Jos.
(1997), Socrates op de Markt.
Amsterdam, Boom.
Kitchener,
Richard. (1990), “Do children think philosophically?”; In: Metaphilosophy, Vol. 21, No. 4, pp. 427, 428.
Leeuw, Karel van
der. (1991), Filosoferen is een Soort
Wereldverkenning; Met bijdragen van Berrie Heesen en Hans Jansen. Tilburg,
Zwijsen.
Leeuw, Karel van
der. (1993), “Experiences with Kio and Gus”; In: Thinking, Vol. 11, No. 1, pp. 31-39.
Leeuw, Karel van
der, and Pieter Mostert. (1987), “Learning to Operate with Philosophical
Concepts”; In: Analytic Teaching,
Vol. 8, No. 1, pp. 93-99.
Lipman, Matthew.
(1988), Philosophy Goes to School.
Philadelphia, Temple University Press.
Lipman, Matthew.
(1991), Thinking in Education.
Cambridge (Mass), Cambridge Univ. Press.
Lipman, Matthew
and Ann Margaret Sharp (eds.). (1978), Growing
up with Philosophy. Philadelphia, Temple Univ. Press.
McCall,
Catherine. (1990), “Young Children Generate Philosophical Ideas”; In: Thinking, Vol. 8, No. 2, pp. 22-41.
Reprinted in: Lipman, Matthew (ed.). Thinking,
Children and Education. Montclair, Kendall/Hunt, 1993, pp. 569-593.
Matthews, Gareth.
(1978), “The Child as Natural Philosopher”; In: Lipman, M. and A. M. Sharp (eds.).
Growing up with Philosophy.
Philadelphia, Temple Univ. Press, pp. 63-77.
Matthews, Gareth.
(1980), Philosophy and the Young Child.
Cambridge (Mass), Harvard Univ. Press.
Matthews, Gareth.
(1984), Dialogues with Children.
Cambridge (Mass), Harvard Univ. Press, 1984.
Matthews, Gareth.
(1992), “Thinking in Stories”; In: Thinking,
Vol. 10, No. 2, p. 1.
Matthews, Gareth.
(1993), “Childhood: The Recapitulation Model”; In: Lipman, Matthew (ed.). Thinking, Children and Education.
Montclair, Kendall/Hunt, pp. 154-160.
Matthews, Gareth.
(1994), The Philosophy of Childhood.
Cambridge (Mass), Harvard Univ. Press, 1994.
Midgley, Mary.
(1996), “Letters to the Editor”; In: The
Guardian, 18 June, p. 14.
Mulvaney, Robert
J. (1993b), “Philosophy for Children in its Historical Context”; In: Lipman,
Matthew (ed.). Thinking, Children and
Education. Montclair, Kendall/Hunt, pp. 393-402.
Murris, Karin.
(1997), Metaphors of the Child’s
Mind; Teaching Philosophy to Young Children; being a Thesis submitted for
the Degree of PhD in Education. University of Hull, October 1997.
Nussbaum, Martha.
(1994), The Therapy of Desire; Theory and
Practice in Hellenistic Ethics. New Jersey, Princeton Univ Press.
Singer, Peter.
(1995), “Coping with Global Change: the need for new values”; In: Critical & Creative Thinking, Vol.
3, No. 2, pp. 1-12.
Slade, Christina.
(1994), “Harryspeak and the Conversation of Girls”; In: Thinking, Vol. 11, Nos. 3, 4, pp. 29-32.
Splitter,
Laurance J. and Ann Margaret Sharp. (1995), Teaching
for Better Thinking; The Classroom Community of Enquiry. Melbourne, Acer.
Sutherland,
Peter. (1992), Cognitive Development
Today; Piaget and his Critics. London, Paul Chapman Publishing.
White, John.
(1992), “The Roots of Philosophy”; In: A. P. Griffiths. The Impulses to Philosophise. Cambridge Univ. Press, 1992, pp.
73-88.
Williams,
Bernard. (1985), Ethics and the Limits of
Philosophy. London, Fontana Press/Collins.
Wilson, John.
(1992), “Philosophy for Children: A Note of Warning”; In: Thinking, Vol. X, No. 1, pp. 17, 18.
Wittgenstein,
Ludwig. (1971), Philosophische
Untersuchungen. Frankfurt am Main, Suhrkamp.